Forging the Chains of Virtue: Aristotle’s Raw Politics of Power

In Aristotle’s Politics, the concept of power is central to his exploration of how societies are organized, maintained, and flourish. For Aristotle, power is not merely about control or dominance but is deeply tied to the ethical and moral foundations of society. His analysis of power encompasses a wide range of contexts, including political authority, …

In Aristotle’s Politics, the concept of power is central to his exploration of how societies are organized, maintained, and flourish. For Aristotle, power is not merely about control or dominance but is deeply tied to the ethical and moral foundations of society. His analysis of power encompasses a wide range of contexts, including political authority, household governance, and the role of virtue in leadership. Understanding power in Aristotle’s thought requires a careful examination of how it operates within different forms of government and its role in the proper functioning of a just society.

In Aristotle’s view, power is inherently linked to governance. He argues that humans are naturally political animals, and as such, they require organized political structures to live fulfilling and virtuous lives. Power becomes a crucial element in the realization of justice and the common good. Aristotle’s Politics offers a nuanced view of power, analyzed through the lenses of different types of constitutions, the nature of authority, and the ethical responsibilities of rulers. Power, in this sense, is not a singular, rigid concept but is understood as varying across political, social, and ethical domains.

Aristotle frequently uses the Greek term “archē” to refer to political power or authority. The term encompasses the idea of “rule” or “beginning,” but in the context of Politics, it specifically refers to the legitimate authority exercised within a political community. Archē denotes the ability to govern and is always considered within a legal and institutional framework. For Aristotle, political power is fundamentally about leadership, not just control, and it must be exercised for the benefit of the community rather than for personal gain.

Aristotle distinguishes between several forms of government, each of which exercises power in different ways. In a monarchy, power is concentrated in the hands of one individual. If the monarch governs for the benefit of the people, this form of government is legitimate and just. However, if the monarch governs for personal gain, the power becomes tyrannical and illegitimate. In an aristocracy, power is vested in a small group of people who are supposed to rule in the interests of the common good. Yet, this form of government can also become corrupt, transforming into an oligarchy, where the few rule in their own interest. Finally, democracy is a form of government where power lies with the majority of citizens. Aristotle is cautious about democracy, warning of the potential for the “tyranny of the majority,” where decisions are made for selfish or short-term interests rather than for the common good.

For Aristotle, political power must be grounded in virtue and justice. Power is legitimate when it is exercised not for personal interest but for the benefit of the polis (the city). Rulers must use their power to promote the well-being of the entire community, and this requires them to be guided by ethical principles. Aristotle emphasizes that the rule of law should be paramount. Laws, rather than individuals, should hold the ultimate power in a society because laws represent rational and stable governance. The role of political power, then, is to implement and enforce laws that promote justice and the common good.

While archē refers to legitimate authority, Aristotle also discusses bia, which refers to power that is exercised through force or coercion. Bia is characterized by the absence of consent and often involves rulers maintaining control through violence, intimidation, or oppression. This form of power is typically associated with tyranny, where the ruler governs through fear and force rather than through the consent of the governed. Aristotle views this type of power as fundamentally illegitimate because it violates the principles of justice and mutual agreement that should underpin political authority.

Aristotle condemns the use of unjust power (bia), arguing that it is corruptive both to the ruler and to the ruled. Power that is exercised through force leads to instability and oppression, as it disregards the common good in favor of the ruler’s self-interest. This form of power is in direct contradiction to natural rule, where authority is based on mutual consent and is directed toward the good of the community. Aristotle believes that legitimate power arises from the willing participation of citizens, and when rulers resort to force, they undermine the very foundations of political life.

Aristotle is clear about the negative consequences of coercive power. Rule by force leads to instability within the political community, as it erodes trust and undermines justice. Citizens who are governed through fear are less likely to feel loyalty to their rulers, and this can result in resistance, rebellion, and ultimately the destabilization of society. For this reason, Aristotle views coercive power as unsustainable in the long run. A ruler who relies on force may be able to maintain control temporarily, but the lack of legitimacy will eventually provoke opposition.

In Aristotle’s ideal political community, citizens play a central role in the exercise of power. In a democracy, power is distributed among citizens through mechanisms such as voting, holding office, and participating in decision-making processes. Citizenship is not simply about enjoying rights and privileges; it is about active engagement in the governance of the polis. Aristotle sees the collective power of citizens as essential to shaping the policies and laws that govern the state. In this way, power is not concentrated in the hands of a few but is shared among the many, creating a more equitable and just society.

For Aristotle, the rule of law is the embodiment of collective power. Laws are the means by which power is distributed and exercised fairly within a community. By adhering to laws, citizens can ensure that power is used to promote justice and prevent the abuse of authority by individuals. Aristotle contrasts the democratic form of power, where the many share authority, with oligarchic power, where a few wealthy elites hold power. In an oligarchy, power is often exercised for personal gain, whereas in a democracy, it is supposed to serve the interests of the community as a whole.

While Aristotle acknowledges the value of citizen participation, he also warns of the dangers associated with excessive collective power. In a democracy, the majority can sometimes use its power to oppress minorities or pursue selfish interests at the expense of justice and the common good. Aristotle refers to this as the “tyranny of the majority.” He emphasizes the need for balance and moderation in the exercise of power, ensuring that no single group dominates to the detriment of others.

Aristotle extends his analysis of power beyond the political sphere to include the household (oikos). In the household, power takes different forms depending on the relationships between individuals. The master-slave relationship is characterized by domination, where the master exercises absolute control over the slave. Aristotle controversially defends this form of power as natural, arguing that some people are naturally suited for subordination. The husband-wife relationship is another form of household power, where the husband holds a form of natural authority over the wife. However, this power is milder than the master-slave relationship and is meant to be exercised with a sense of care and protection. Finally, in the parent-child relationship, power is exercised for the benefit of the child’s well-being and development, rather than for domination.

Aristotle believes that the power dynamics within the household mirror the larger political structures of society, but on a smaller and more personal scale. Just as in the polis, household power is hierarchical, but it should be used in accordance with natural justice. The head of the household has a responsibility to ensure the well-being of all its members, and power should be exercised benevolently, with the aim of promoting harmony and stability within the household.

While there are similarities between household power and political power, Aristotle makes a clear distinction between the two. Power within the household is private and is exercised in the context of personal relationships, whereas political power is public and involves the governance of the entire community. The methods and purposes of exercising power in these two domains differ significantly. Political power is concerned with the common good and is exercised through laws and institutions, while household power is more informal and is directed toward the care and development of family members.

Aristotle also speaks of power in terms of dynamis, meaning the ability or capacity to achieve a particular goal or function. In the context of political power, dynamis refers to the ability to govern effectively. Those who possess the intellectual and moral virtues are best suited to exercise power because they have the knowledge and wisdom necessary to make decisions that benefit the community. In this sense, power is not merely about having control over others, but about having the capacity to lead wisely and justly.

The concept of arete (virtue) is central to Aristotle’s understanding of power. For Aristotle, power is legitimate only when it is exercised by individuals who possess moral excellence. Those who are virtuous have the ethical responsibility to use their power for the common good, rather than for selfish or corrupt purposes. This link between power and virtue is crucial to Aristotle’s political theory. Only those who are morally upright and just are capable of ruling in a way that promotes the well-being of the polis.

Ultimately, Aristotle believes that the best use of power is to lead wisely and promote the flourishing of the political community. Power is not about domination or control, but about ensuring that the community thrives and that justice is upheld. Aristotle’s concept of just power is rooted in the idea that rulers must exercise their authority in a way that promotes harmony, justice, and the well-being of all citizens. In this way, power becomes a means to achieve the common good, rather than an end in itself.

For Aristotle, power is not inherently good or bad; rather, its value depends on how it is used. When power is exercised for the benefit of the community and guided by virtue, it is a positive force that enables the polis to thrive. However, when power is used for selfish purposes or maintained through coercion, it becomes corrupt and destructive. Power, then, is both a means to achieve justice and the end goal of ensuring the common good.

Aristotle draws a clear distinction between legitimate power and illegitimate power. Legitimate power (archē) is based on justice and virtue and is exercised for the benefit of the community. Illegitimate power (bia) is based on force and compulsion and serves the interests of the ruler rather than the ruled. This distinction is crucial to Aristotle’s political theory, as it highlights the ethical responsibility of rulers to use their power in a just and virtuous manner.

The proper use of power is deeply tied to ethical governance in Aristotle’s thought. Rulers must be guided by virtue and must exercise their authority in a way that promotes the well-being of the polis. Power, for Aristotle, is not about self-interest or domination, but about ensuring the flourishing of the entire community.

 

Join the Club

Like this story? You’ll love our monthly newsletter.

Thank you for subscribing to the newsletter.

Oops. Something went wrong. Please try again later.