Schmitt’s Political Form: Decoding Democracy’s Unity Crisis

Introduction Carl Schmitt’s concept of politische Form—translated as “political form”—is a cornerstone of his political thought. Developed most prominently in Römischer Katholizismus und politische Form (1923) and elaborated further in Verfassungslehre (1928), the idea of political form ties together some of Schmitt’s most crucial concerns: sovereignty, authority, representation, and the structural order of political life. …

Introduction

Carl Schmitt’s concept of politische Form—translated as “political form”—is a cornerstone of his political thought. Developed most prominently in Römischer Katholizismus und politische Form (1923) and elaborated further in Verfassungslehre (1928), the idea of political form ties together some of Schmitt’s most crucial concerns: sovereignty, authority, representation, and the structural order of political life. For Schmitt, political form is not a merely abstract category; it is a tangible expression of the fundamental decisions and metaphysical commitments that sustain political unity and legitimacy. In contrast to liberal democracy’s emphasis on procedure, neutrality, and individual rights, Schmitt insists that true political order requires a concrete, authoritative form that binds the political community together and enables decisive action, particularly in moments of crisis.

This essay will explore the meaning of political form in Schmitt’s work, its theological and historical background, and its implications for constitutional theory and political legitimacy. It will do so by examining his interpretation of the Catholic Church as a paradigmatic political form, his critique of liberal proceduralism, and his understanding of sovereignty as a decision-making authority. Through this, we will see that political form for Schmitt is not only a matter of institutions but also a reflection of a society’s moral and metaphysical commitments.

I.  The Meaning of “Politische Form” in Römischer Katholizismus

In Römischer Katholizismus und politische Form, Schmitt identifies the Catholic Church as a model of political form. This analysis is not primarily theological; it is political in the sense that Schmitt sees the Church as a visible, structured organization capable of embodying authority, unity, and continuity. He draws attention to the Church’s hierarchical nature, its capacity for representation, and its transcendent claims—features that, for Schmitt, stand in stark contrast to the fragmented and procedural nature of liberal political institutions.

By “political form,” Schmitt refers to the mode of appearance or manifestation of political authority in a concrete and structured way. It is how power is visibly and symbolically organized, how it assumes shape, and how it is legitimated within a given political community. Political form is not reducible to governmental machinery or administrative technique; rather, it is a qualitative expression of unity, an embodiment of collective will, and a framework for authority. In the Catholic Church, Schmitt sees a political form that unites metaphysical claims with institutional hierarchy. Its unity is not based on the aggregation of individual interests, as in liberal democracy, but on a shared, transcendent vision of order.

For Schmitt, liberal modernity lacks this form. Liberalism’s insistence on neutrality, its elevation of individual rights above collective authority, and its procedural conception of politics all contribute to a kind of political formlessness. Liberal democracies, in Schmitt’s view, are plagued by internal contradictions: they aim to be neutral among competing values yet make authoritative decisions; they claim to protect freedom yet depend on coercive institutions. Lacking a coherent political form, they become arenas of conflict without a unifying authority.

Schmitt’s analysis of the Catholic Church serves as a foil to liberalism. The Church, with its centralized authority, institutional permanence, and claim to universal truth, exemplifies what Schmitt sees as a genuine political form: a system in which representation, order, and sovereignty are visibly and authoritatively maintained. It provides not only an institutional structure but also a moral and metaphysical foundation that sustains the political community across time.

II.  Political Form as Representation and Unity

Central to Schmitt’s conception of political form is the idea of representation. In contrast to liberal theories that treat representation as a mere mechanism of electoral accountability, Schmitt conceives of it as a substantive and symbolic act. Representation, for him, is the process by which the unity and identity of the political community are embodied in an authority that can speak and act on its behalf.

In this sense, representation is not merely descriptive or numerical; it is existential and authoritative. The representative institution or figure is not simply a mirror of public opinion but a unifying force that articulates and enacts the collective will. This is one reason why Schmitt admires the Catholic Church: it claims to represent a divine order that transcends the contingencies of individual preference and historical flux. The Pope, the hierarchy, the liturgy—all serve to instantiate a visible order that embodies a unified conception of truth and authority.

By contrast, liberal democracy often disaggregates representation into a multiplicity of competing interests. Parliaments, political parties, and civil society organizations all claim to speak for “the people,” yet there is no unified principle that binds them together. Schmitt sees in this pluralism a tendency toward fragmentation. Without a concrete form of representation that can impose unity, the political order becomes unstable and incoherent.

This concern with unity leads Schmitt to link political form with sovereignty. Political form is the condition under which sovereign authority can be exercised, and sovereignty, in turn, is the power to make decisions that preserve or restore political unity—especially in times of exception. In liberal theory, sovereignty is often diffused through checks and balances, divided powers, and legal procedures. For Schmitt, however, this diffusion undermines the very capacity of the political community to respond decisively when its existence is at stake.

 

III.  Constitutional Theory and the Elaboration of Political Form in Verfassungslehre

In Verfassungslehre (1928), Schmitt moves from the ecclesiastical model to a detailed analysis of the modern state and its constitutional form. Here, political form is no longer illustrated primarily by the Catholic Church but by the constitution of the state itself. The constitution, for Schmitt, is not merely a legal document or procedural framework—it is the concrete manifestation of a political decision about the fundamental structure of authority.

A genuine constitution, Schmitt argues, is grounded in a politische Entscheidung—a political decision—that defines who holds power, how it is exercised, and in what form the political community will be organized. This decision is not procedural but existential: it constitutes the identity and unity of the state. In other words, a constitution expresses the political form of the state; it is the legal embodiment of a prior act of political will.

Schmitt distinguishes between the Constitution in the substantive sense and mere constitutional laws or statutes. The former is a foundational act that establishes the form of political unity, while the latter are technical rules that may change over time. This distinction reflects Schmitt’s opposition to positivist legal theory, which treats all legal norms as equal and denies the need for a foundational political decision.

In Schmitt’s framework, the political form of the state is intimately connected to its sovereign power. Sovereignty is not a legal function but a political reality: it is the capacity to decide on the exception. In moments of crisis, when normal rules and procedures no longer suffice, the sovereign must act to preserve the unity and existence of the state. The political form must therefore be robust enough to concentrate authority and enable decisive action. A constitution that disables sovereignty in the name of procedure, Schmitt argues, is a weak and unstable political form.

IV.  The Four Elements of Political Form

Schmitt’s conception of political form, as outlined across these works, can be summarized in four interrelated dimensions:

  1. Unity and Sovereignty

A political form must ensure the unity of the political community. Without unity, there is no capacity for collective action or decision-making. Sovereignty is the expression of this unity in the form of a decisive authority. Schmitt’s famous formulation—“Sovereign is he who decides on the exception”—underscores the link between sovereignty and political form. A polity without the capacity for sovereign decision lacks a true political form, for it cannot respond to existential threats.

2. Representation

Representation is not simply a democratic mechanism but a way of embodying the political community. A political form must make the people visible in a concrete way—through institutions, symbols, or leadership. The representative authority must unify, not merely reflect, the political body.

3. Order and Structure

Political form is the ordering principle of political life. It provides a framework within which authority is exercised, laws are made, and political life is conducted. A formless polity, governed only by procedure and lacking a clear structure of command and representation, is liable to dissolve into conflict and indecision.

4. Decisionism

Finally, a political form must enable the making of fundamental decisions—especially in times of exception, when ordinary laws and procedures fail. Schmitt’s critique of liberalism is rooted in its inability to confront this necessity. Liberal democracy, in attempting to depoliticize and proceduralize politics, undermines the possibility of sovereign decision. Thus, it lacks a true political form.

V.  The Theological-Political Dimension

It is impossible to understand Schmitt’s concept of political form without considering its theological underpinnings. Schmitt often insisted that “all significant concepts of the modern theory of the state are secularized theological concepts.” This applies to sovereignty, representation, and order—all of which, in his view, find their origins in theological doctrines, particularly within Christianity.

The Catholic Church exemplifies this legacy. Its hierarchical structure, sacramental order, and doctrine of representation (especially in the Eucharist and the papacy) provide, in Schmitt’s view, a model of political form that unites theological and political authority. The Church is both a spiritual and institutional power—transcendent in claim, yet concrete in form.

Modern liberalism, by contrast, is grounded in the rejection of such theological authority. Its emphasis on individual autonomy, rational procedure, and moral neutrality reflects a secular worldview that denies any transcendent political form. For Schmitt, this secularization leads not to liberation but to the erosion of political unity and authority.

VI.  Political Form and the Crisis of Modernity

Schmitt’s reflections on political form are not merely historical or theoretical. They are responses to what he saw as the crisis of modern politics. The Weimar Republic, where Schmitt was politically active, embodied for him the dangers of formlessness: a state riddled with parliamentary indecision, lacking strong leadership, and unable to confront existential threats.

The absence of a clear political form in Weimar, Schmitt believed, left the state vulnerable to internal division and external collapse. In this context, his call for a strong sovereign authority and a concrete political form was not a purely academic argument—it was a plea for political salvation.

Critics have rightly noted the dangers in Schmitt’s thought, particularly its authoritarian implications. His valorization of decision, his disdain for liberalism, and his involvement with the Nazi regime raise serious moral and political concerns. Nevertheless, his concept of political form remains a powerful critique of proceduralism and a compelling account of the conditions necessary for political unity.

 

Conclusion: The Relevance of Political Form

Carl Schmitt’s concept of political form remains one of his most enduring and provocative contributions to political theory. It challenges us to think beyond legalistic and procedural models of politics and to confront the foundational questions of authority, unity, and representation. In Römischer Katholizismus, Schmitt sees the Catholic Church as an exemplary political form—an institution that unites metaphysical vision with hierarchical order. In Verfassungslehre, he applies this idea to the modern state, arguing that a genuine constitution must embody a concrete political form rooted in sovereign decision.

For Schmitt, political form is not a technical matter; it is the visible manifestation of a society’s fundamental political commitments. Without such form, there can be no sovereignty, no unity, and ultimately no order. Liberal democracies that neglect this insight risk descending into fragmentation and formlessness. While we must remain critical of Schmitt’s political allegiances, his insistence on the necessity of political form challenges us to reflect more deeply on what sustains political life in the modern world.

Join the Club

Like this story? You’ll love our monthly newsletter.

Thank you for subscribing to the newsletter.

Oops. Something went wrong. Please try again later.